Four items
appear below
1 Free Will in
Heaven
2 Assumption of
Heaven
3 Assuming the
Assumption
4 Assuming the
Assumption – A Reply
Free Will in Heaven
Bruce Bennie
(Investigator 139, 2011
July)
In my article on
'Goodness and Evil' (Investigator #134), I put forward
the view that to allow human free will to operate provides a
significant reason as to why God allows evil and why we experience it.
That is, to be fully human is to have the capacity to be morally and
rationally responsible. Kevin Rogers (Investigator # 135) responded
that "Christianity offers the hope of a new world order (heaven), where
there will be no evil. Will there be free-will in heaven? If so, how
can God prevent the re-emergence of evil?"
This is a
question that surfaces quickly when Christians consider the
role of free will in choosing between right and wrong. If such an
ability constitutes an essence of the image of God within us, and if
that image is to be perfected in Heaven, then how can we find ourselves
without free will? Yet, if there is free will in Heaven, how can we
guarantee that we will not, at some stage in eternity, use that free
will to choose evil once again? It is this uncertainty that causes
Christians concern with the idea and this uncertainty focuses around
the 'risk' we may choose evil over the good. Indeed many struggle to
understand why God allowed this element of risk in the first place.
Thiselton
draws from the late Australian philosopher, J. L. Mackie, in
acknowledging that "for God to create Adam and Eve was a 'hell of a
risk'…when divine foreknowledge would tell what (at least) might
occur…a more restricted 'freedom' could have ensured conditions for
'right action' with less risk." (Thiselton, 2002, p. 109).
On the
whole, many of us prefer situations where there is less risk.
But to find a way of a 'more restricted freedom' can confront us with
the question of determinism. Craig defines determinism as "for every
event that happens, there are conditions such that, given them, nothing
else could have happened…its happening was caused or necessitated by
prior factors" (Moreland and Craig 2003, p. 268). If God had arranged a
world 'where nothing else could have happened' and fashioned it where
only good moral choices were possible and evil was not a possibility,
then good moral choices would have become the ruling factor. In light
of the extent of evil and suffering in this world, would that not have
been a better choice on God's behalf?
Yet many
believe we also have libertarian free will, which holds that
for one to be truly free, we must have control over our actions and our
will. If we have to choose between options or possibilities there is
nothing determining how we will make that choice. Rather than a choice
that happens as a response to predetermined factors, a libertarian
choice originates solely from our own 'casual powers'.
Is Mackie
right and would some form of determinism have been a more
successful way for God to keep the potential for evil from escalating
to the extent we have seen in human experience? Is libertarian
free will the cause of all our problems, a sort of moral loose canon
within the heart of humanity from whence comes the problem of evil?
Determinism
would carry the idea of 'less risk' but libertarian free
will conveys what we really prefer. For a hard line, absolute
determinism where all events are pre-determined or caused by another
agency or influence would appear to rob people of being responsible
agents, accountable for their actions. But it would affect other things
as well. Receiving praise or assigning blame would become meaningless.
And if every event was determined by other factors, we would simply
have to resign ourselves to playing the hand of cards we were dealt. So
again, we are back to acknowledging that to be fully human appears to
require we have something like libertarian free will. Yet some
Christians are concerned that if God is sovereign, and determines
everything, does libertarian free will usurp that sovereignty? In
answering this, Geisler responds: "It is sufficient to note that God
sovereignly delegated free choice to some of his creatures. There was
no necessity for him to do so; he exercised his free will…Only absolute
freedom would be contrary to God's absolute sovereignty. But human free
will is a limited freedom. Humans are not free to become God
themselves. A contingent being cannot become a Necessary Being"
(Geisler 1999, p. 263).
If God's
sovereign rule is absolute, but human free will is not, then
it suggests that some things may in fact be determined. Is there a
middle way between these two sides?
Compatibilism
appears to provide a middle road through complete
determinism and unrestricted freedom. It allows a measure of both to
operate with the view that both are in fact compatible – freedom is not
completely determined, nor is it completely free of any predetermined
factors. God still has sovereign control while allowing human beings as
morally responsible beings.
Yet there
is still more involved than just wanting to reduce the risk
of choosing evil. Having a free will also radically affects the kind of
relationships we can have. For genuine love, trust and affection to
arise in a free being it must not be compelled. It is the Christian
view, Hick affirms, that human beings should have a relationship with
their Creator, and that any worship or obedience that was not freely
given would lack any real value in God's eyes. "We should, in relation
to God, be mere puppets, precluded from entering into any truly
personal relationship with Him" (Hick 1968, p. 308-310). It is seen
then as logically impossible for God to receive free, un-forced love
from human beings while already having put conditions into place that
would force such a response. To be forced to love God is not to be free
to love God. Indeed, is true love ever forced?
Yet what
if the choice to love or to rebel against God was at last
fully and finally removed? Certainly it is free will that is involved
in making that choice to love or reject, but what if that particular
choice was one that no longer had to be made by human beings? What if
the choice made in this life concerning people's response to God (for
or against) was the choice people were eternally confirmed in.
Certainly for some this would raise the question of those who were,
because of mental illness, unable to make a decision in this area, or
those who had never heard the gospel, or those who hold a universalist
view that God would make it possible for everyone to be restored into
the divine presence, but for now, let us consider this question in the
broad strokes.
What if
there awaits in Heaven the full flush reality of what
theologians have referred to as the Beautific Vision, a vision so
all-consuming it would encompass all and any possible worlds? Where
human beings would consciously enter into the presence of an
omniscient, omnipresent, Necessary Being who was pure actuality in
terms of knowledge, coherence and morality. A Being not contingent upon
any other but fully realised, sufficient in itself, inexhaustible and
unlimited in mind, nature and power, and sustaining all things? Where
the 'hiddeness of God' was finally and irrevocably revealed?
And here
we discover the 'hope of a new world order' Kevin spoke of.
Here, Christians affirm, is the hope of the gospel fully realised -
Christ in you the hope of glory (Colossians 3:4). For it shall be in
Heaven that Christians will share fully in Christ's nature, and as
Christ gave himself completely to the glory of God, even so shall
believers desire to know nothing other than that same glory. The free
choice to choose Christ on this earth will yield its full reward in his
presence in eternity. The presence of God will expel all darkness from
the human heart and God will dwell in us and we in him. Any action
taken that would violate that relationship, to choose against God or to
operate outside of him, will be finally seen to have a vileness that
makes it repulsive. It will be like the betrayal experienced when one
partner commits adultery against the other. But the hope of this 'new
world order' is that we will no longer desire to live outside of the
immediate presence and knowledge of God, there will be no other
alternatives that will have any appeal or pull on us. The nature of
Christ, to which we will be inseparably bound and infinitely content,
will be the guarantee that we will not choose evil in heaven.
Indeed, we have as much desire to sin in Heaven as Christ had to sin on
earth. Which Christians believe was no desire whatsoever.
In
the light of such a 'Vision', would there be any choice left
to make? Would there be any choice possible? Could we become entirely
objective, unbiased and calmly decide the issue of God's existence with
a detached air of rational consideration? Would that capacity be
available to us anymore? Would we discover we have already chosen in
this regard after all? Yet will God, who has created body and mind,
soul and spirit, have also made a path where determinism and freedom
will find their perfect expression?
Christians
believe that what will constitute the ruling reality of
Heaven will be the full expression of God's divine nature and glory.
All eternal life, power and strength will flow out of that nature and
glory, and all joy, adoration and purpose will be found as a response
to it. So the nature of Heaven will be fully determined by the very
Being of God. Yet free will can exist in that such a Being will be
freely embraced in adoration and delight, from which no dissent or
separation will again be sought or desired. It may be more the case
than not that Heaven will indeed allow a compatibilist response, where
a free act is one "that is causally determined but done voluntarily"
(Pojman 1998: p. 257). Augustine's confession will at last have become
every believer's eternal experience, that "you made us for yourself and
our hearts find no peace until they rest in you" (Augustine 1961
ed; p 21).
Yet some
may ask if God's direct presence banished darkness, why did
Lucifer and a third of the angels choose to rebel against God and fall
from Heaven? It may be for the same reason Adam and Eve were given a
choice to obey in the Garden, a choice that had by necessity to be
allowed each human being. For if God is truly the Being that has
captivated the attention of theologians, stirred up the probing
questions of philosophers, and garnered the worship of countless human
beings throughout history, then the 'hiddeness of God' could be seen to
be the very protection of the ability to make a free will choice in the
first place.
Now for
some reading these words it will perhaps seem to be mere
fantasy. They may protest that talk of a Necessary Being does not give
immediate licence to equate such a Being with the God of the Bible.
Issues involving the historicity of Jesus may surface or questions
regarding the reliability of the Biblical records. And these are all
valid questions and will no doubt continue to fuel contributions to the
Investigator for many issues to come. But for the
purposes of this article I have endeavoured to look at the Christian
'hope' Kevin Rogers spoke of and suggest some thoughts as to how free
will may exist in Heaven without sin becoming an inevitable recurrence.
Bibliography
Augustine, St. 1961
ed, Confessions, trans. R. S.
Pine-Coffin, Penguin Books, England.
Geisler, N 1999, Baker
Encyclopedia of Christian Apologetics,
Grand Rapids, Michigan.
Hick, J 1968, Evil and
the God of Love, Collins, London.
Moreland, J P and Craig, W
L 2003, Philosophical Foundations for a
Christian Worldview, IVP, Illinois.
Pojman, Louis P 1998, Philosophy
of Religion An Anthology, 3rd
ed, Wadsworth Publishing, New York.
Thisleton, A 2002, A
Concise Encyclopedia of the Philosophy of
Religion, Oneworld Publications, Oxford.
ASSUMPTION of HEAVEN
(Investigator 140, 2011
September)
I read Bruce
Bennie's article Free Will in Heaven (No. 139,
page 57), and although I found it interesting it reminded me of a
Medieval scholastic discussing the properties of unicorn horn. Said
scholastic should have first obtained proof that unicorns existed
before putting quill to parchment.
I
apologise to Bruce if this comment comes across as being rather
blunt. But really, what evidence is there that humans can survive
death, and that there is a heaven to which souls can go?
If Bruce
replies I hope he isn't going to bombard us with Biblical
quotations. All this can prove is that a particular person believed a
particular thing at a particular point in time.
Kirk
Straughen
'Assuming' the Assumption' –
A Reply to Kirk Straughen
Bruce Bennie
(Investigator
141, 2011 November)
Kirk Straughen
responded to my article concerning free will in Heaven
(#139) with a reply entitled 'Assumption of Heaven' (#140). Kirk made
the observation that I reminded him of a medieval scholar pondering the
properties of a unicorn, the thought being there seemed as much
evidence for the existence of a unicorn as there was for Heaven.
That is, none.
It was a
side bar from addressing the issue of moral beings responding
to God, and did not address that issue. But I took it that Kirk was not
focusing on that point as such, but this business of 'assumptions'.
After all, it is hard to delight over holding opera tickets to a
theatre that doesn't exist. Why worry about the implications of free
will in Heaven if we don't have any hard evidence Heaven is actually
there? Kirk rejects we have any such evidence and so any discussion of
Heaven's role in terms of morality or life after death is simply an
assumption on my part.
Philosopher
Peter Kreeft has looked at this issue of Heaven, and
addresses twenty nine objections to Heaven's existence. In looking at
objection 2, he considers the argument that there is no scientific
evidence for Heaven. In reply he writes “the objector assumes that
whatever there is no scientific evidence for, does not exist…But there
is no scientific evidence for that assumption; it cannot be proved by
the scientific method. It is simply an assumption – in fact, it is an
arbitrary decision and desire to narrow the bounds of reality to the
bounds of the scientific method. It is a decision of the will, not the
intellect” (Kreeft, p. 264).
Assumptions
form a part of our worldview. Because our worldviews are
shaped by our perceptions, early education and community expectations,
we often simply assume this is indeed how the world operates. So there
often appears to be little reason to examine or evaluate our views,
until life experience raises new questions or they suddenly clash with
another's view of the world and we are forced to face our unexamined
assumptions. If we assume the scientific method is the most reliable
way of gaining knowledge, or that without airtight evidence the whole
case is not worthy of any serious investigation, then we are making
assumptions of our own. That assumption is what Timothy Keller
refers to as 'strong rationalism' (Keller, p. 128). But where do we
find the airtight evidence that assures us that only a 'strong
rationalism' can provide us with the only knowledge worth knowing?
Certainly
those demanding airtight proof for God's existence will be
continually frustrated. It can seem as if God does play 'hide and seek'
with his creation. Some can assert there is no proof for the simple
reason God does not exist. But here again is the assumption that no
proof of existence must mean no existence. Tim Keller, in talking with
a young scientist who was frustrated that no proof of God could
rationally survive all counter arguments, put aside this business of
'proofs' and viewed the classic arguments rather as 'clues' (Keller, p.
128). To regard the existence of a fine-tuned universe, the regularity
of nature, the impression that the world seemed to have been fashioned
with human beings in mind, and a moral sense within human beings of all
races, could stand as clues that pointed toward the existence of a God.
And we are free to ask what worldview best explains all these 'clues'?
These
clues have fascinated and engaged people of all walks of life for
thousands of years, and continue to do so. Not with the force to
overwhelm us, but enough to woo our thoughts to turn toward the big
questions of life. It is almost as if the human heart has a receiver
that picks up this 'signal' from a far distant shore, that can never be
found on a map, or in a test tube, but seems to be echoing from the
world and universe around us.
It is the
assumptions we will make about that signal that will
determine how we will evaluate the clues.
Bibliography
Peter Kreeft, Handbook
of Christian Apologetics, Inter Varsity
Press,
Illinois, 1994.
Timothy Keller, The
Reason For God, Belief in an Age of Scepticism,
Hodder, England, 2009.
Reply To Bruce Bennie On
Heaven
(Investigator 142, 2012
January)
I have read
Bruce's reply (No. 141, page 54) to my comments concerning
heaven. Unfortunately, he hasn't offered any evidence for the existence
of heaven. Rather (in my opinion) he seeks to obfuscate the issue by
claiming that lack of proof isn't evidence that God and heaven don't
exist, and implies that their existence is possible for this reason:
Certainly
those demanding airtight proof for God's existence will be
continually frustrated. It can seem as if God does play 'hide and seek'
with his creation. Some can assert there is no proof for the simple
reason God does not exist. But here again is the assumption that no
proof of existence must mean no existence. (Page 55)
Is this
argument convincing? I shall modify the above quotation and let
my readers be the judge:
Certainly
those demanding airtight proof for the existence of unicorns
will be continually frustrated. It can seem as if unicorns do play
'hide and seek' with those looking for them. Some can assert there is
no proof for the simple reason unicorns do not exist. But here again is
the assumption that no proof of existence must mean no existence.
Have I
proven unicorns exist by this verbal sleight of hand? Have I
shown that the existence of unicorns is even probable? If this kind of
argument isn't convincing for unicorns then why should it be convincing
for heaven?
Kirk
Straughen